socrates on persuasion, truth, and courtroom argumentation in plato.docx
![资源得分’ title=](/images/score_1.gif)
![资源得分’ title=](/images/score_1.gif)
![资源得分’ title=](/images/score_1.gif)
![资源得分’ title=](/images/score_1.gif)
![资源得分’ title=](/images/score_05.gif)
《socrates on persuasion, truth, and courtroom argumentation in plato.docx》由会员分享,可在线阅读,更多相关《socrates on persuasion, truth, and courtroom argumentation in plato.docx(12页珍藏版)》请在淘文阁 - 分享文档赚钱的网站上搜索。
1、Title:Socrates on Persuasion, Truth, and Courtroom Argumentation in Platos ApologyAuthor:Dale JacquetteCommentary: C.W. Tindale 2003 Dale Jacquette1. Socrates9 TrialOn trial fbr his life, as portrayed in Platos Apology, Socrates appears to sharply divide philosophy from rhetoric. He articulates a pr
2、eference for philosophy as the pursuit of truth over and above the sophistry of rhetorical devices that can be used to persuade an audience without regard for the truth. Closer examination, however, reveals that Socrates9 juridical arguments, including his efforts to justify the philosophical quest
3、for truth, can be understood as constituting a complex polemical strategy.The conflict between philosophy and rhetoric remains as pertinent today as in Socrates5 time, and has particular significance for contemporary argumentation theory. We should ask, even as we hear echoes of the same problem in
4、the Athenian courtroom where Socrates defended the practice of philosophy, how best to define the concept of a good argument. The problem posed by Socrates back in 350 BCE can be described in these terms: Is a good argument one that effectively persuades an audience regardless of its truth, or one t
5、hat logically entails true conclusions, regardless of its persuasiveness or lack thereof? Truth and persuasion need not always conflict, and the force of truth is often a key element in persuading an audience. The question nevertheless remains, since truth and persuasion also sometimes stand at odds
6、, whether the primary purpose of argument is persuasion or truth. What makes for a good argument when truth and persuasion do not happily go hand in hand?Socrates, in the end, does not persuade enough of the jurors at his trial to save himself from the fatal cup of hemlock. Let us leave aside the po
7、ssibility that a significant number of the jurors were cynically prepared to condemn Socrates regardless of the evidence and argument they were presented, and assume that all made up their open minds on the basis of what they heard from the prosecution and defense. Most impartial readers of Plato5 s
8、 dialogue and Xenophons independently confirming reportage maintain that his arguments were brilliant, powerful rebuttals of the charges raised against him, elegant, incisive, and penetrating. Nor does it matter with respect to the truth-persuasion dichotomy in argumentation theory that we today are
9、 more persuaded by Socrates, apologia than were his fellow Athenians who voted for his death. Socrates was undoubtedly speaking not only to the members of the jury but to future generations including ourselves who are witness to the injustice to which he was subjected. The immediate audience fbr whi
10、ch Socrates reasoning was intended was not swayed by his dialectic, when, so to speak, it would have made a difference. Are proponents of the definition of a good argument as persuasive regardless of its truth prepared to say that the very same argument is both good and not good depending on its rec
11、eption by different audiences at different times and under different circumstances? If we are tallying up advantages and disadvantages of alternative ways of characterizing a good argument, we might observe that no highest flights of rhetoric. For evidence of this we need look no further than the in
12、ternal content of the speech he makes in his own defense. He is anything but disorganized, his remarks are not offered at random, as he warns, but follow a well-structured plan of attack directed toward systematically refuting the offenses with which he is baselessly charged. He makes subtle almost
13、subliminal use of the same kinds of rhetorical devices that he supposedly renounces. Without ringing his hands or bringing in his wife and children to weep before the jury and plead indecorously for clemency, Socrates nevertheless makes it understood that he is married with young children, that desp
14、ite his vigor he is an old man who ought to command respect rather than suffer humiliation, that he has had a distinguished military career in the service of the city, that far from being an atheist he has acted always in obedience to Apollo and has followed the expected religious observances, and f
15、inally that he has benefited rather than harmed his fellow citizens.The accusations raised against him, moreover, are confused, self-contradictory, and unfounded in fact. What, we must still ask after all these years, is he supposed to have done? Did he murder someone or cut their purse, or rape or
16、break into a home or bear false testimony? Of course, he did none of these things. His only crime was to discuss philosophy freely, in both senses of the word, with persons who chose to hear him speak, in which he tried always to let the better argument prevail, and in which the pursuit of truth led
17、 him to conclude among other things that democracy was not the best form of government for the ideal city-state. In the end, he mounts a stunning defense not only of his own conduct but of the philosophical way of life.Yet, predictably, from his standpoint, the arguments he offers, as sound and irre
18、futable as they may appear to us today, are simply not good enough. If the fix was in from the beginning, as Stone suggests, then it is unclear that any of the courtroom theatrics in which Socrates refuses to engage would have made any difference anyway. In that case, he was doomed from before the m
19、oment he was summoned to the lawcourt.As the jurors prepare to drop their ostraka or pottery shards with their names etched on them into the urns to be counted for or against the accused, Socrates indicates again that he will not resort to the usual methods of pleading for mercy:This, and maybe othe
20、r similar things, is what I have to say in my defense.Perhaps one of you might be angry as he recalls that when he himself stood trial on a less dangerous charge, he begged and implored the jury with many tears, that he brought his children and many of his friends and family into court to arouse as
21、much pity as he could, but that I do none of these things, even though I may seem to be running the ultimate risk. Thinking of this, he might feel resentful toward me and, angry about this, cast his vote in anger. If there is such a one among you 一 I do not deem there is, but if there is - I think i
22、t would be right to say in reply: My good sir, I too have a household and, in Homers phrase, I am not bom “from oak or rock“ but from men, so that I have a family, indeed three sons, gentlemen of the jury, of whom one is an adolescent while two are children.Nevertheless, I will not beg you to acquit
23、 me by bringing them here. Why do I do none of these things? Not through arrogance, gentlemen, nor through lack of respect for you. Whether I am brave in the face of death is another matter, but with regard to my reputation and yours and that of the whole city, it does not seem right to me to do the
24、se things, especially at my age and with my reputation (34b6-e4).If Stone is right, it would not have mattered no matter how logically sound, evidentially well-supported or rhetorically persuasive his defense had been. For the offenses with which he is charged, of corrupting the youth and dishonorin
- 配套讲稿:
如PPT文件的首页显示word图标,表示该PPT已包含配套word讲稿。双击word图标可打开word文档。
- 特殊限制:
部分文档作品中含有的国旗、国徽等图片,仅作为作品整体效果示例展示,禁止商用。设计者仅对作品中独创性部分享有著作权。
- 关 键 词:
- socrates on persuasion truth and courtroom argumentation in plato persuasion truth
![提示](https://www.taowenge.com/images/bang_tan.gif)
链接地址:https://www.taowenge.com/p-86332314.html
限制150内